Adventuring With Philosophers

More than a century ago, an early torts scholar (Pollock) wrote that, when it came to causation, lawyers and judges shouldn’t go adventuring with philosophers. Many modern Canadian lawyers and judges are likely more familiar with Sopinka J.’s admonition in Snell v. Farrell against “abstract metaphysical theory” – the claim that causation is “essentially a practical question of fact which can best be answered by ordinary common sense rather than abstract metaphysical theory.”

On the other hand, fewer modern Canadian lawyers or judges probably know that a recent article written jointly by a law professor and philosophy professor – an article which certainly has some discussion that some might label “metaphysical theory” – contains a passage that Pollock and Sopinka might have wholeheartedly approved:

An increasing number of philosophers seem to be willing to take the concept of causal connection as a primitive (unanalyzable) concept – one of the conceptual atoms out of which we build more complex concepts or ideas. But one does not need to be overly cynical to wonder whether this embrace is not born out of sheer frustration with the inability to say something interesting yet true about what constitutes the essence of causation. In any event, if the law is waiting for philosophers to offer something better than a prephilosophical grasp of what is involved in one thing causing another, the law had better be very patient indeed.

See R. Fumerton and K. Kress, “Causation And The Law: Preemption, Lawful Sufficiency And Causal Sufficiency” (2001), 64 Law and Contemporary Problems 83 at 105.

And, more than a half-century ago, a famous philosopher, Bertrand Russell, had this to say about the John Locke and Locke’ philosophy. 

He is always sensible, and always willing to sacrifice logic rather than become paradoxical. He enunciates general principles which, as the reader can hardly fail to perceive, are capable of leading to strange consequences; but whenever the strange consequences seem about to appear, Locke blandly refrains from drawing them. To a logician this is irritating; to a practical man, it is proof of sound judgement. Since the world is what it is, it is clear that valid reasoning from sound principles cannot lead to error; but a principle may be so nearly true as to deserve theoretical respect, and yet may lead to practical consequences which we feel to be absurd. There is therefore a justification for common sense in philosophy, but only as showing that our theoretical principles cannot be quite correct so long as their consequences are condemned by an appeal to common sense which we feel to be irresistible. The theorist may retort that common sense is no more infallible than logic. But this retort, though made by Berkeley and Hume, would have been wholly foreign to Locke’s intellectual temper.

[Emphasis added]. See Bertrand Russell, A History of Western Philosophy (New York: Simon & Schuster, Inc., 1967) at 606 (paperback) (at 630 in the 1946 George Allen & Unwin edition).

So perhaps Canadian judges and lawyers can afford to go adventuring with philosophers now and again, albeit properly chaperoned and warded, if only to find ammunition for their petards.

After all, isn’t it said that one should keep one’s friends close and one’s enemies closer?

Comments

  1. David Collier-Brown

    It is also arguably true that valid reasoning from agreed facts cannot lead to error, save where the facts are found to be incorrect.

    The problem with principles is that, in principle, they are descriptive and correct, while in fact they may be generalizations from sets of facts that contain errors.

    Discovering contradictions and “practical consequences which we feel to be absurd” are the tests of such principle and of facts, something which courts are very capable of, without having to define what in the world “common sense” means.

    The latter is an adventure I don’t care to have!

    –dave (and yes, I am a philosopher by trade) c-b

  2. “It is also arguably true that valid reasoning from agreed facts cannot lead to error, save where the facts are found to be incorrect

    .

    Assuming those determining the meaning of “error” agree on the meaning of “error” which (I think) presumes agreement on what “valid” means in “valid reasoning”. But common law lawyers (who know their history) can always quote the other Holmes, too, and claim that the “life of the [common] law is experience not logic”. I added “common”.

    We could debate, until the cows come in, whether law’s “valid” is, needs to be, or even ought to be, the same as science’s (writ large)”valid”.

    We wouldn’t accept a judge – other than on Monty Python – declaring that he or she applies the principle of Jabberwocky. Yet (in my view) that’s what the common sense mantra amounts to. Or it’s a black hole which, unlike those in our universe, doesn’t allow any information about it to escape.

    Common sense is (in my view) the juridical equivalent of the juror’s “wah wah wah”. See (now) Ian Binne, “Science in the Courtroom: The Mouse That Roared” 2007 56 U.N.B.L.J. 307 at 314-15 for the source of that phrase. He wasn’t referring to the content of judicial analysis, there.

    A leading American tort scholar recently used the phrase “virtually nonsensical gibberish” to describe some American jurisprudence on causation in tort. Others have used phrases such as “vacuous incantations”. That’s often enough accurate for our jurisprudence. I’m (sometimes) not sure ours is entitled to the “virtually”.

    That doesn’t mean the decisions the judges made are necessarily wrong; nor even that the decision made can’t be supported as the better decision. It just means that there’s a disconnect between the rules which are supposed to have been applied, or purport to have been applied, and the result.